Is Charity Enough
Discussing libertarianism inevitably involves answering the question "what about the poor"? And then, when libertarians suggest that those that want to help the poor can do so through private charity, the discussion inevitably ends with a doubt that charity would be enough. The answer is, of course, "enough for what?" It certainly isn't the be all and end all. Firstly, it is plain that the poor in the more capitalist tend to be much better off than the poor in the less capitalist countries. The claim that libertarians want to defend the interests of the rich only and don't care about the poor, when shown in this light is utterly falacious: Capitalism, where it has been allowed to work, has been better for the poor than socialism has, both in terms of actual wealth, ensuring that even if the poor get a smaller slice of the pie, it is a much bigger pie they get a slice of, and in terms of equality: The division between the rich and poor is less in more capitalist countries than, say, between racking members of the Comintern compared to the poorest person in the USSR. Libertarianism would also mean an end to corporate welfare, redistribution to the rich, and the provision of monopolistic privilege by the state. And, lastly, libertarianism would also mean the freeing of the creative energies of people themselves to come up with theri own solutions to problems and hazards, including the risk of poverty and the inability to provide for oneself. That means the development of mutual aid and insurance arrangements.
So, libertarians do not simply rely on private charity. However, what can be said in defense of charity and in answer to this question, would it be enough? Well, the question itself is odd. The supposition is that people don't want to help the poor, or those in need, or those incapable of helping themselves. But if that is the case, then why would they ever vote for a government to force them to do so? As David Friedman wrote,
So, if the vast majority of people are too selfish to help those in need, then it plainly follows that no democratic institutions would result in the transfer of money from the majority to the poor. People wouldn't be likely to vote for such a government. But people do vote for such governments. Of course, one must not neglect various facts, such as the fact that the state employs between about a fifth and a quarter of the entire workforce of the UK (the NHS is, I hear, the biggest employer in Europe), and so that inevitably means that a huge part of the electorate will be made up of people who's continued income depends on voting in support of various government activities and policies. It also means that some of the most powerful pressure groups on government policy will be public sector, as opposed to private sector, unions. Given this, support for an extensive welfare state is likely to come, in large part, from those actually employed by that welfare state, not necessarily from those it serves, or from those exclusively interested in using it to help people. Beyond this, the welfare state also helps people who are not poor, not needy. The NHS is there fore all who want to use it, rich or poor (in theory, at least). Likewise for schooling, and so many other things. Some of those non-poor who support the welfare state may well do so because it helps them, not because they care for the needy who cannot help themselves, then.
However, in the end, surely a large reason that people vote for welfare statist policies is because they support and favour the use of democratic institutions to help the poor and the needy and those who cannot help themselves. Libertarians say, then, that if people want to help the poor, then they don't need governments to force them to do it, and if they don't want to help the poor, then it is odd to think that they will support governments to force them to do it.
Of course, the response to that is that the defenders of the welfare state are voting to force the unwilling to help, as well as themselves. However, surely the number of unwilling people isn't that big. I find it totally incredible that they would comprise any significant part of the electorate. In fact, I would use the unpopularity of libertarianism as evidence that it is not. Hardly anybody likes libertarianism, and the principle reason that they dislike libertarianism, it seems to me, is because libertarians say that there is a big problem in forcing people to contribute to looking after the poor, and the reason that most people reject such a position is because most people have a fear that, without such force, the poor would not be looked after. It should, therefore, follow that most people care for the poor considerably, and would, then, continue to give money to help them were they not forced to.
So, to build an answer to the question, we can accept that, given the popularity of the welfare state even amongst those that are not net beneficiaries of it, support enough to maintain its existence, it is reasonable to assume that most people would continue giving large portions of their income to help those in need. Lets assume that a third of them would, or that total voluntary donations would amount to a third of the amount that government provides now.
Beyond this we have the question of how many now in receipt of welfare are actually people that those who support the welfare state for altruistic reasons actually want to help. By this I mean, how many of these people are actually capable of providing for themselves. Mary Ruwart wrote,
Of course, this is from America. People may say that the UK is different, that our welfare state is more discriminating and better safe guarded against abuse and fraud. I'm not sure what possible grounds they could argue such a ridiculous thing on - so far as I can tell, welfare fraud is widespread. Such a thing has formed the basis of James Bartholomew's work on the welfare state, and I would direct them there. Mary Ruwart's claim was that "Giving money to those who could work results in less money for those who can't." People may think that money about benefit fraud and welfare mothers is only for the selfish and greedy minded, but this is a real reason to oppose such a thing: Less welfare fraud means more for those who actually need it. Private charity is more discriminating than government. Its funds more limited. If people don't think that a particular charity is helping, and helping more than anybody else can, then they will stop donating. This means that charities are under a competitive pressure to be successful, and it means that if funds are being wasted on those that don't need them rather than those that do, then a charity is wasting the funds of its donors - funds that they can simply stop donating if they discover such a thing, unlike those that fund the welfare state. Mary Ruwart writes,
Make a conservative guess that half of the people actually on welfare or claiming some sort of benefit are actually capable of supporting themselves, and that private charity would cut off all support for such people. Now add in our previous position that, absent government compulsion, people would voluntarily donate funds equal to half the current money that the government provides for the poor. That would mean that the actual needy, instead of those who are able to support themselves, would recieve just as much without a welfare state.
However, we needn't stop there, since we have the effectiveness of government versus charity itself to bring in. James Rolph Edwards has an excellent paper on this in the Journal of Libertarian Studies. He reminds us that "Some fraction of each dollar taxed will always be absorbed in wages and salaries of the administrative bureaucracy, costs of purchasing, powering, maintaining and replacing equipment, buildings, etc., and other overhead costs. Only the remainder will actually be received by the target population in the form of cash or in kind payments. Many advocates of compulsory income redistribution have tended to ignore this inconvenient fact altogether in their writings, however. Indeed, most of the public discussion proceeds with an implicit assumption of costless, dollar-for-dollar income transfers." Given this, it is very worth considering where the overheads will be higher, how much money gets absorbed in costs - in state welfare, or in private charity. Edwards writes,
Edwards suggest that actually this two-thirds figure is conservative: Charity Navigator only records charities that are tax exempt 501 (c)(3) organisations required to provide informational tax returns. That excludes religious organisations. Such organisations often use donated labour, and so can exclude labour from their total costs. Why this difference in costs?
Where does this leave our argument now? Mary Ruwart again provides the answer: "Of course, public welfare gives over 2/3 of every tax dollar we give them to overhead (e.g., salaries of the bureaucrats who administer the program). Private charities, however, give 2/3 of every dollar to those who need help. By switching to private distribution, we'd cut overhead in half. In other words, we'd double the dollars available to the needy once again."
So, we have the fact that so many people who are not themselves net beneficiaries or employees of the welfare state continue to vote for or support welfare statist policies itself indicates a good chance that huge numbers of people would continue to donate money were the compulsion removed. On a conservative estimate I said that a third of the present government expenditure could be raised through voluntary donations.
I then established a conservative suggestion that half of the total revenue spent by the government on welfare is collected by those that can support themselves, and would be denied support by private charities. That means doubling the remaining funds for anybody left. That gives us two thirds or the present expenditures.
Lastly we have the superior efficiency of charity over government, averaging twice as efficient. So we can double our two thirds of government expenditure. The result is that leaving support for the needy could well leave us with 33% more support, in financial terms, for the actual needy than is presently provided by the state.
Is charity enough? It is more than enough
So, libertarians do not simply rely on private charity. However, what can be said in defense of charity and in answer to this question, would it be enough? Well, the question itself is odd. The supposition is that people don't want to help the poor, or those in need, or those incapable of helping themselves. But if that is the case, then why would they ever vote for a government to force them to do so? As David Friedman wrote,
Suppose that one hundred years ago someone tried to persuade me that democratic institutions could be used to transfer money from the bulk of the population to the poor. I could have made the following reply: 'The poor, whom you wish to help, are many times outnumbered by the rest of the population, from whom you intend to take the money to help them. If the non-poor are not generous enough to give money to the poor voluntarily through private charity, what makes you think they will be such fools as to vote to force themselves to give it?'
So, if the vast majority of people are too selfish to help those in need, then it plainly follows that no democratic institutions would result in the transfer of money from the majority to the poor. People wouldn't be likely to vote for such a government. But people do vote for such governments. Of course, one must not neglect various facts, such as the fact that the state employs between about a fifth and a quarter of the entire workforce of the UK (the NHS is, I hear, the biggest employer in Europe), and so that inevitably means that a huge part of the electorate will be made up of people who's continued income depends on voting in support of various government activities and policies. It also means that some of the most powerful pressure groups on government policy will be public sector, as opposed to private sector, unions. Given this, support for an extensive welfare state is likely to come, in large part, from those actually employed by that welfare state, not necessarily from those it serves, or from those exclusively interested in using it to help people. Beyond this, the welfare state also helps people who are not poor, not needy. The NHS is there fore all who want to use it, rich or poor (in theory, at least). Likewise for schooling, and so many other things. Some of those non-poor who support the welfare state may well do so because it helps them, not because they care for the needy who cannot help themselves, then.
However, in the end, surely a large reason that people vote for welfare statist policies is because they support and favour the use of democratic institutions to help the poor and the needy and those who cannot help themselves. Libertarians say, then, that if people want to help the poor, then they don't need governments to force them to do it, and if they don't want to help the poor, then it is odd to think that they will support governments to force them to do it.
Of course, the response to that is that the defenders of the welfare state are voting to force the unwilling to help, as well as themselves. However, surely the number of unwilling people isn't that big. I find it totally incredible that they would comprise any significant part of the electorate. In fact, I would use the unpopularity of libertarianism as evidence that it is not. Hardly anybody likes libertarianism, and the principle reason that they dislike libertarianism, it seems to me, is because libertarians say that there is a big problem in forcing people to contribute to looking after the poor, and the reason that most people reject such a position is because most people have a fear that, without such force, the poor would not be looked after. It should, therefore, follow that most people care for the poor considerably, and would, then, continue to give money to help them were they not forced to.
So, to build an answer to the question, we can accept that, given the popularity of the welfare state even amongst those that are not net beneficiaries of it, support enough to maintain its existence, it is reasonable to assume that most people would continue giving large portions of their income to help those in need. Lets assume that a third of them would, or that total voluntary donations would amount to a third of the amount that government provides now.
Beyond this we have the question of how many now in receipt of welfare are actually people that those who support the welfare state for altruistic reasons actually want to help. By this I mean, how many of these people are actually capable of providing for themselves. Mary Ruwart wrote,
During the 1980s, I rented to welfare recipients. Ninety percent of my tenants were able-bodied women with children who simply chose welfare instead of work. Indeed, one woman who tried to give me friendly advice suggested that I stop fixing up the apartments at night and give up my day job. "Have some kids and get on welfare so that you can enjoy your life," she counseled me. Although I did not take her advice, many young women did. Low-income teens often told me that they became pregnant in order to receive welfare checks and establish their own residences. The more children they had, the bigger their welfare stipend.
In 1992, New Jersey eliminated part of the monthly increase that women received for new children. Even though stopping this stipend only decreased the welfare package 4%, births to welfare mothers went down by 10%. Clearly, many women were getting pregnant as a means of self-support. No wonder that one in eight children now receive some form of government "aid."
Why would someone choosing to conceive children as meal tickets and live on welfare? By the mid-90s, a person would have to earn $5.50 to $17.50 per hour (depending upon your state) to get more after-tax benefits than they'd receive on welfare! Of course, choosing welfare instead of work didn't give a person job experience or regular raises, so choosing poverty as a teen was generally a life sentence.
When Ohio required capable welfare recipients to work, 40% of them decided that they didn't need help after all. Oregon tried to place its able-bodied welfare population in jobs by offering employers a subsidy to take them. Once welfare recipients found that they were going to have to work for someone, 80% went out and found an unsubsidized job. Clearly, a great deal of the welfare population simply chooses not to work when tax dollars, usually in excess of what they would initially earn, are readily available. Giving money to those who could work results in less money for those who can't.
In 1987, Wisconsin began requiring people on aid to seek or train for work. By 1997, Wisconsin had 55% fewer families on welfare than it did in 1987, while the rest of the nation experienced an average increase of 16%. In other words, Wisconsin's work program cut welfare by 71%!
Of course, this is from America. People may say that the UK is different, that our welfare state is more discriminating and better safe guarded against abuse and fraud. I'm not sure what possible grounds they could argue such a ridiculous thing on - so far as I can tell, welfare fraud is widespread. Such a thing has formed the basis of James Bartholomew's work on the welfare state, and I would direct them there. Mary Ruwart's claim was that "Giving money to those who could work results in less money for those who can't." People may think that money about benefit fraud and welfare mothers is only for the selfish and greedy minded, but this is a real reason to oppose such a thing: Less welfare fraud means more for those who actually need it. Private charity is more discriminating than government. Its funds more limited. If people don't think that a particular charity is helping, and helping more than anybody else can, then they will stop donating. This means that charities are under a competitive pressure to be successful, and it means that if funds are being wasted on those that don't need them rather than those that do, then a charity is wasting the funds of its donors - funds that they can simply stop donating if they discover such a thing, unlike those that fund the welfare state. Mary Ruwart writes,
In 1987, Wisconsin began requiring people on aid to seek or train for work. By 1997, Wisconsin had 55% fewer families on welfare than it did in 1987, while the rest of the nation experienced an average increase of 16%. In other words, Wisconsin's work program cut welfare by 71% !
Let's assume that Wisconsin's experience was atypical and that nationwide, only 50%, rather than 71%, of the people on welfare are capable of supporting themselves. Private charities would be likely to weed out such people. Thus, if we simply gave the equivalent of the welfare budget to churches and other private charities for distribution, twice as much help would go to the truly needy--virtually overnight!
Make a conservative guess that half of the people actually on welfare or claiming some sort of benefit are actually capable of supporting themselves, and that private charity would cut off all support for such people. Now add in our previous position that, absent government compulsion, people would voluntarily donate funds equal to half the current money that the government provides for the poor. That would mean that the actual needy, instead of those who are able to support themselves, would recieve just as much without a welfare state.
However, we needn't stop there, since we have the effectiveness of government versus charity itself to bring in. James Rolph Edwards has an excellent paper on this in the Journal of Libertarian Studies. He reminds us that "Some fraction of each dollar taxed will always be absorbed in wages and salaries of the administrative bureaucracy, costs of purchasing, powering, maintaining and replacing equipment, buildings, etc., and other overhead costs. Only the remainder will actually be received by the target population in the form of cash or in kind payments. Many advocates of compulsory income redistribution have tended to ignore this inconvenient fact altogether in their writings, however. Indeed, most of the public discussion proceeds with an implicit assumption of costless, dollar-for-dollar income transfers." Given this, it is very worth considering where the overheads will be higher, how much money gets absorbed in costs - in state welfare, or in private charity. Edwards writes,
Of course it is also true of private charities dependent on voluntary donations that they have costs absorbing part of their revenue, but there is a huge difference in the efficiency with which they operate relative to government. Contrary to Okun, public income redistribution agencies are estimated to absorb about two-thirds of each dollar budgeted to them in overhead costs, and in some cases as much as three-quarters of each dollar. Using government data, Robert L. Woodson (1989, p. 63) calculated that, on average, 70 cents of each dollar budgeted for government assistance goes not to the poor, but to the members of the welfare bureaucracy and others serving the poor. Michael Tanner (1996, p. 136 n. 18) cites regional studies supporting this 70/30 split.
In contrast, administrative and other operating costs in private charities absorb, on average, only one-third or less of each dollar donated, leaving the other two-thirds (or more) to be delivered to recipients. Charity Navigator www.charitynavigator.org), the newest of several private sector organizations that rate charities by various criteria and supply that information to the public on their web sites, found that, as of 2004, 70 percent of charities they rated spent at least 75 percent of their budgets on the programs and services they exist to provide, and 90 percent spent at least 65 percent. The median administrative expense among all charities in their sample was only 10.3 percent.
Edwards suggest that actually this two-thirds figure is conservative: Charity Navigator only records charities that are tax exempt 501 (c)(3) organisations required to provide informational tax returns. That excludes religious organisations. Such organisations often use donated labour, and so can exclude labour from their total costs. Why this difference in costs?
The basic reason for this large differential in costs between private and public agencies is not difficult to see. Depending largely on voluntary contributions, most private agencies are under strong pressures to operate efficiently and keep costs low. Benevolent citizens naturally wish a large fraction of their donations to reach the needy, and many will not keep donating to an agency that does not accomplish that. Donors can select among private nonprofit charities, and competition between charities for donations tends to insure efficiency. Public aid agencies, in contrast, are budgeted their funds by Congress, which obtains them through compulsory taxation. These agencies are not under competitive pressures to keep costs down that are remotely equivalent to those of private charities. Indeed, their incentives may be much the opposite, as Niskanen (1994) has argued. Yet another factor promoting efficiency of private charities is that those operating at levels of inefficiency comparable to the average government agency are often prosecuted—by the government (which never applies the same standards or threat to its own agencies)—for fraud. Pressure on private charities to avoid such prosecution, and the bad publicity and loss of public trust resulting, is strong.
Where does this leave our argument now? Mary Ruwart again provides the answer: "Of course, public welfare gives over 2/3 of every tax dollar we give them to overhead (e.g., salaries of the bureaucrats who administer the program). Private charities, however, give 2/3 of every dollar to those who need help. By switching to private distribution, we'd cut overhead in half. In other words, we'd double the dollars available to the needy once again."
So, we have the fact that so many people who are not themselves net beneficiaries or employees of the welfare state continue to vote for or support welfare statist policies itself indicates a good chance that huge numbers of people would continue to donate money were the compulsion removed. On a conservative estimate I said that a third of the present government expenditure could be raised through voluntary donations.
I then established a conservative suggestion that half of the total revenue spent by the government on welfare is collected by those that can support themselves, and would be denied support by private charities. That means doubling the remaining funds for anybody left. That gives us two thirds or the present expenditures.
Lastly we have the superior efficiency of charity over government, averaging twice as efficient. So we can double our two thirds of government expenditure. The result is that leaving support for the needy could well leave us with 33% more support, in financial terms, for the actual needy than is presently provided by the state.
Is charity enough? It is more than enough
1 Comments:
Absolutely excellent. Don't ever stop blogging - you are an inspiration. :-)
Post a Comment
<< Home